Self-Reference, Math Foundations and Gödel’s Incompleteness

Self-reference is (too?) common in real life, as many of our sentences begin with I. Talking to persons who abuse of self-references can be tiring. And in mathematics, watching at self-referencing objects has turned into a nightmare, starting with British mathematician Bertrand Russell. In 1901, based on a reasoning on such objects, he proved that mathematics were non-sense.

What the hell? Is this a joke?

No! Let’s see how he did it!

Russell’s Paradox

Bertrand Russell actually worked with the most fundamental mathematical objects: sets. Sets are simply collections of other mathematical objects. In very fundamental mathematics, sets are actually the only objects. So, really, what sets are is a collection of sets.

Waw… I feel like this is going to get abstract…

Let’s do the reasoning with Science4All articles to make it less abstract! I’ll replace the phrase “a set contains another set” by “a S4A article contains a link towards another S4A article“. Even more simply, we’ll say that a S4A article points to another S4A article. We can now apply Russell’s exact reasoning.

OK…

Now, there’s a simple self-referencing concept about S4A articles: A S4A article either points to itself or not.

What do you mean?

Well, let’s consider the article you’re currently reading. This is a S4A article. And it has the following link towards itself (hover or click to verify that it really is the case!). So it points to itself. But most of other articles don’t point to themselves.

OK… So far so good.

Good. Because we are getting to Russell’s great idea. He imagined himself writing a S4A article which points at all S4A article which don’t point to themselves. Let’s call this article Russell’s S4A article.

Russell's Article

The S4A article called Self-Reference you’re currently reading points to itself, so Russell’s S4A article wouldn’t point to Self-Reference. But most of other S4A articles don’t point to themselves. Russell’s S4A article would point to them.

OK… I don’t see what’s so great about Russell’s S4A article…

As Russell writes it, he has to choose whether his S4A article will point to itself! Think about it. If it does point to itself…

It shouldn’t be in Russell’s S4A article which doesn’t point at S4A article which points to themselves!

Yes! But if it doesn’t point to itself…

It should be Russell’s S4A article which lists all S4A articles which don’t point to themselves!

Yes!!! Let’s recapitulate with the following figure:

Russell's S4A Article

So Russell’s S4A article can’t point at itself nor not point to itself! It can’t exist!

Exactly! Yet, mathematics at Russell’s time allowed to construct such theoretical S4A article… which means that it allowed the existence of something that doesn’t exist! No wonder why 1901 mathematics was non-sense!

More generally, Russell’s paradox consists in replacing the verb contain by any other verb. Here are some similar paradoxes we can obtain by doing so:

  • Imagine a barber who shaves everyone who doesn’t shave themselves. Does he shave himself?
  • Imagine a painter who paints everyone who doesn’t paint themselves. Does he paint himself?
  • Imagine a blogger who blogs about everyone who doesn’t blog about themselves. Does he blog about himself?

Another example of similar paradoxes is the following extract from The Office.

Awesome!

There are lots of puzzles based on self-referencing. Here’s a nice one. Assume you are faced with two doors. One leads to heaven, the other to hell. But the only way for you to know is by asking one single question to the angel in front of you… who may in fact by the devil. The thing is, if he’s an angel, he can’t lie, but if he’s the devil, he has to lie. What question should you ask?

Hum…

Think about it. I’ll give the answer at the end of this article.

OK… But is Russell’s paradox that bad? I mean, it is a weird mathematical trick…

It is bad! It is extremely bad! Because one contradiction in mathematics imply that all mathematics is non-sense! Think about it. A lot of reasonings in mathematics are based on reductio ad absurdum: You start by assuming something and show that this assumption implies a contradiction. This proves that what you assumed is wrong. But now, you can assume anything, like for instance that 0=0, and say that it leads to Russell’s paradox. This mathematically proves that 0≠0, which in turn can imply something like 1=0. Russell’s paradox proves that mathematics in 1901 was non-sense!

This must have been a huge schock!

It was! This image from the awesome graphic novel Logicomix, which narrates the foundation crisis in mathematics in early 1900s through the story of its main contributors, depicts Russell’s stupefaction when he discovered the paradox:

Russell in Logicomix

At this point, Russell knew that everything in mathematics and logics was destroyed!

Waw!!! Are you saying that I’ve been learning something wrong all along???

Just like you, mathematicians of the beginning of the 20th century, including Gottlob Frego and David Hilbert, were devastated! So they rejected classical assumptions of mathematics, now known as the naive set theory. And they searched for a better-defined formalism. And the 20th century has produced incredibly surprising and counter-intuitive results regarding such formalisms. For instance, they enable to prove that $1+2+4+8+16+…=-1$, as you can read it in my article on infinite series! But there’s even more troubling… Since it’s a little complicated, I’ll get to this in the third section of this article.

Recursion and Fractals

What I’m now going to show you is that self-referencing isn’t all bad. As long as it’s done properly…

What do you mean?

One extremely useful self-referencing in computer science is known as recursion. It is based on the idea that if you can break down your problem into simpler versions of itself.

Chocolate Bar

What?

Let me give you an example. Consider a chocolate bar, the kind of which is made of well-ordered squares. like the one on the right. Now, imagine a bar with $2 \times n$ squares. But your kids or students only like to have $1 \times 2$ pieces of chocolate. How many ways are there to divide your bar into $1 \times 2$ pieces of chocolate?

What do you mean?

The following figure displays 6 different ways to divide a $2 \times 6$ bar of chocolates into $1 \times 2$ pieces.

Chocolate Pieces

How many ways are there in total?

There seems to be a lot… Do you really want me to count them all?

No. I want you to find the answer without counting! And it’s possible, thanks to the magic of recursion!

OK… So you want me to break the problem into smaller version of itself… Are you talking about problems for smaller rectangles?

Yes!

Hum… A little help, please?

Sure. Look at the top right corner square of your bar. It needs to belong to a $1 \times 2$ piece. But there’s only two possibilities for this piece: It’s either horizontal or vertical. Now, if it is vertical, then you end up with a $2 \times (n-1)$ chocolate bar! That’s a smaller version of this problem!

But what about if it is horizontal?

Well, if it is horizontal, you have to notice that the two pieces below the horizontal piece must be grouped into another horizontal piece. And you are left with filling…

a 2x(n-2) chocolate bar! That’s a smaller version of the problem too!

Yes! Let’s recapitulate with the following figure:

Chocolate Bar Recursion

So, in one case, the number of ways to divide the chocolate bar is the solution of the problem for $n-1$. In the other case, it’s the solution for $n-2$! Overall, the solution for $n$ is the sum of the solution for $n-1$ and $n-2$. So if the solution for 4 is 5 and the solution for 5 is 8, then the solution for 6 is 5+8=13. And such reasoning can very easily be written as an algorithms for computers!

Is this how it’s done?

Our reasoning is actually incomplete. If we simply tell the computer to search for solutions $n-1$ and $n-2$ to solve the problem for $n$, we will have a big issue: Our computer will be searching solutions of -1 and -2 to find the solution of 0, and then search for solutions of -3 and -4 to find the solution of -2… and so on! To avoid this, we need a base case, that is, a case which does not depend on any other case. Well, in fact, here, we need two base cases, since we search for solutions at both $n-1$ and $n-2$.

We’re actually here defining a very famous sequence, called the Fibonacci sequence. It’s very famous and has nice properties. In particular, it is very tricky to compute! If you can, please write about it.
So all recursive algorithms must have a base case?

Yes! A recursive algorithm is defined by base cases, and, for other cases, relations to other simpler cases. By simpler, I mean, cases which are strictly closer to base cases.

Can you give other examples of recursion?

Sure! The most famous ones are probably Euclid’s algorithm to find the greatest common divisor, the solution to the tower of Hanoi and the state-of-the-art optimization technic called dynamic programming.

All these algorithms are dramatically beautiful! If you can, please write about them!
Waw! Recursion is great!

And it’s not limited to algorithms! A typical example of recursion in a definition is the following definition of ancestors: An ancestor is either one of your parents or an ancestor of your parents. Note that the base case here is a little hidden: The recursion relation is only defined if one actually has parents… This means that the base case is about people without parents! But do they exist? Well, that’s a tough conundrum of Darwin’s theory of evolution

Waw! Recursion is awesome!

It is! But there’s something even better! In mathematics, you don’t necessarily need base cases to define recursion, as long as the simpler cases are “much simpler”! This amazing remark led to the construction of the wildest mathematical objects such as the Cantor set, the Kock snowflake and the Mandelbrot set. These objects are obtained by repeating their global appearances at lower scales of themselves. They are commonly known as fractals. They are probably the most beautiful creation of modern mathematics, with surprising applications in a large variety of fields, including biology, seismology, stock market analysis, information technology… and even in cinematography! Check this extract from Marcus du Sautoy’s show on shapes made with BBC:

Find out more, by reading Thomas’ great article on fractals to know what they really are! You should also check this great video to find out more about applications.

Gödel’s Incompleteness Theorems

Let’s now get back to the problem of the inconsistency of mathematics.

Oh yeah! You said that the 20th century provided surprising results!

Yes. But remember how bad things were at its beginning: Mathematics were proven to be non-sense! From 1910 to 1925, to set mathematics straight, Bertrand Russell and Alfred North Whitehead wrote and rewrote the Principia Mathematica. It redefined new rules of mathematics, called axioms. The list of these axioms forms what is known as a theory. Russell and Whitehead’s theory aimed at forbidding self-referencing.

Did it work?

A few years later, in 1931, one of the greatest mathematician of all time, Kurt Gödel, reacted. He claimed that Russell and Whitehead hadn’t managed to forbid self-referencing. In fact, any theory which is interesting enough to include basic mathematics like natural numbers cannot forbid self-referencing!

Really? How did he prove it?

He actually constructed such a phrase. Its construction is a little bit complicated. It’s based on a mapping of symbols of maths with numbers. This gives you a set of digits. A theorem is then a succession of such symbols. It therefore corresponds to a number made of digits. In fact, each theorem corresponds to a unique number. And, similarly, so does each proof. These numbers are called Gödel-numbers. Now, I’m not going go into the details, but Gödel proved that Gödel-numbers could be manipulated such that one could be eventually created such that it talks about itself.

Actually, just because the phrase doesn’t have a proof within the theory doesn’t make it not true. Indeed, a larger theory which contains it may be able to prove the phrase. Thus, phrases can be considered true, without having proof within the theory. But I’m now talking about things I barely understand. If you can, please write about these things!
What does this Gödel-number correspond to?

Well, loosely stated, it says that there is no proof to itself. That’s Gödel’s amazing construction! Out of any theory interesting enough, the following phrase exists: The theorem you’re reading has no proof.

Waw! Indeed, this shows that self-referencing cannot be avoided!

Worse than this! The self-referencing phrase I have given cannot be proven false nor true! If it is true, then you should have a proof. Yet, it says that there is no proof. On the opposite, if it is false, this means that it has a proof. But a theorem that has a proof is true! So unless the theory is inconsistent in which case a theorem can be true and false, Gödel’s phrase is neither true nor false! Such a phrase is called undecidable.

So mathematics will always have theorems which are neither true nor false!

That’s pretty much Gödel’s first incompleteness theorem! Roughly, it says that consistent theories are necessarily incomplete.

For a more accurate proof, you should check this video. It’s nicely done (although I’m not a big fan of the music!), and it goes more into the abstract details.

The greatest illustration of this surprising theorem is the astonishing continuum hypothesis I explained in my talk More Hiking in Modern Math World.

Waw! That’s disturbing! But that’s not that big a deal, is it? I mean… At least mathematics are consistent!

I have never said that! What I said is that if they are consistent, then they are incomplete. But we’re not even sure they are consistent. We haven’t proven the consistency of mathematics!

Really? So a new Bertrand Russell could destroy all of mathematics tomorrow?

Yes!

Oh my god! Then I guess that proving the consistency of mathematics is the most crucial open problem of mathematics!

Surprisingly, no! Once again, that’s because of Kurt Gödel. Indeed, he also proved that theories can never prove themselves consistent! After all, a theory which talks about its consistency, that’s very much a self-reference!

But Russell did prove that naive set theory was inconsistent…

It is possible for a theory to prove its inconsistency. But if there is no proof of its inconsistency, then there’s also no proof of its own consistency. This is known as Gödel’s second incompleteness theorem. Check this extract from my talk A Trek through 20th Century Mathematics where I present both Russell’s paradox and Gödel’s second incompleteness theorem!

I haven’t gone deeper into the details, because it’s too hard for me to explain here, as well as too hard for me to even understand! But if you can, please write more about axiomatization, consistency and incompleteness!

Let’s Conclude

As opposed to what mathematicians thought 100 years ago, self-referencing is not bad at all! It’s an essential part of theories. And if done nicely, it can provide an extremely nice framework, like for recursion and fractals. In fact, self-reference is an essential part of some wonderful pieces of art. Think about Abed referring to TV shows in the TV show Community and Stargate SG1’s 200th episode, the classic movies usual suspects and fight club, or novels like Frankenstein and Le dernier jour d’un condamné (sorry I’m not that familiar with non-French classics). This technic in arts is commonly known as the mise en abyme (here’s a little bit more of French for you to learn!). Here’s one great example by Vihart, about herself making videos:

Hey, what’s the solution of the doors to heaven and hell conundrum?

Oh yeah, that’s right! It’s in the food for thoughts below!

More on Science4All

Type Theory: A Modern Computable Paradigm for Math Type Theory: A Modern Computable Paradigm for Math
By Lê Nguyên Hoang | Updated:2016-01 | Views: 12899
In 2013, three dozens of today's brightest minds have just laid out new foundation of mathematics after a year of collective effort. This new paradigm better fits both informal and computationally-checkable mathematics. There is little doubt that it will fundamentally change our perspective on rigorous knowledge, and it could be that, in a few decades, the book they published turns out to be the bedrock of all mathematics, and, by extension, all human knowledge! Have a primer of this upcoming revolution, with this article on type theory, the theory that the book builds upon!

Construction and Definition of Numbers Construction and Definition of Numbers
By Lê Nguyên Hoang | Updated:2016-02 | Views: 9164
Although they have been used for thousands of years, an actual definition of numbers was given less than a century ago! From the most fundamental level of set theory, this article takes you to the journey of the construction of natural, integer, rational, real and complex numbers.

The Limitless Vertigo of Cantor's Infinite The Limitless Vertigo of Cantor's Infinite
By Lê Nguyên Hoang | Updated:2015-12 | Views: 4079
No one believed him. Not even fellow mathematicians. They thought he was wrong. They thought he was crazy. Even he ended up doubting himself and went crazy. And yet, he had mathematically proved it all. Georg Cantor had figured out how to manipulate the infinite. Even more remarkable, he showed that there were actually several infinities; and some are bigger than others!

The Surprising Flavor of Infinite Series The Surprising Flavor of Infinite Series
By Lê Nguyên Hoang | Updated:2020-01 | Views: 11401
1+2+4+8+16+...=-1, as proven by Henry Reich on Minute Physics! Now, as a mathematician, I must say that his proof is far from being rigorous. In fact, anyone familiar with the surprising flavor of infinite series should not find it convincing. Surprisingly though, his proof can be rigorously and naturally justified! Find out how!

From Britain's coast to Julia set: an introduction to fractals From Britain's coast to Julia set: an introduction to fractals
By Thomas C | Updated:2016-02 | Views: 4779

One comment to “Self-Reference, Math Foundations and Gödel’s Incompleteness

Leave a Reply

Your email address will not be published. Required fields are marked *